La Noción De Mímesis En Aristóteles (the Notion Of Mimesis In Aristotle)
(Barbero, Santiago)
The book of Santiago Barber approaches a subject that is receiving renewed interest: the Poetics of Aristotle, resource of the unquestionable last word, appears to have fallen into oblivion for the past three or four decades. It traces the occurrence of the term in the different works, in the Rhetoric and, principally, in the Poetics, with particular regard to how to proceed methodologically in unravelling the concept. It analyses the vital relationship between mimesis and action, the value of mimesis for the universal in art - and the individual (as representation), the logic of the mimesis in Aristotle and the logic model that applies to the study of tragedy, and the nexus that establishes itself between mimesis and pleasure. A particularly interesting subject is that related to what S. Barber calls the "translation" of the mimesis, which he understands to be only possible if attention is paid to the cultural and ideological context in which Aristotle exposes an idea or set of ideas. The section dedicated to the archaic presents the rise of the mimesis concept, which as such is not in Homer but without Homer is incomprehensible. S. Barber synthesizes it in one protean formula: "alternative reality with respect to nature or to everyday reality". Mimesis expresses itself in a product that is Other but that does not hide its referential intention; through the skills of the artist, it evokes the idea of prodigy and the sensation of astonishment: "one would say that the statue is for speaking", as would say the Mime of Herodas. The path leads to the Platonic idea of mimesis, which already incorporates ontological considerations, ethics and pedagogics. The product of the mimesis no longer refers exclusively to the sensible world but also to one of ideas; Plato vies to oppose mimesis and diegesis, postulates the virtues of direct and indirect discourse, enters into precisions that lay the way to Aristotle, who, nevertheless, rebels against all previous "poetics of enthusiasm". In fact, many of the problems that arise are of translation (already using the term without quotes); in general, it is retaken from the Latin imitatio, but without incorporating the concomitancies that this word can have in, for example, the Ars Poetica of Horace, where to imitate always signifies - "to reproduce something exterior to the work"; if there is "servile imitation", it is a question related to the incapacity of the artistic producer. Something similar occurs with the word "representation", that S. Barber insinuates comes from the idea of Else - a simple reproduction, connoted with fingere which does not meet many Aristotilean requirements. In fact, these semantic linkings have broken with the irruption of non-figurative art, as much in the form of abstract painting as in the different variables of the non-realist literary vanguard (that, nonetheless, continue to constitute mimesis forms). In his conclusions S. Barber presents a series of precisions; here only those in the text that have resulted in being the most illuminating can be presented: mimesis and art are almost synonymous in the archaic world; "to be" and "to be represented" contain an equivalence with "to be" and "to resemble"; more than with "imitation", the original Greek word is related to similarity (that in Aristotle is made intentionally explicit) and artistic reality is more alternative than imitative.
Resumos Relacionados
- Poetics
- Poetics
- Nichomachean Ethics
- Luiz Costa Lima - Vida E Obra
- Timario, Or How The Man Has Suffered
|
|